Competition
Restrained by a Higher Good (Part 2)
Who
Really Believes in Unfettered Competition?
Unfettered competition, most
free-market advocates insist, is the most necessary component of a successful
economic system. And the most convincing argument supporting this assertion
just happens to be communism. Ask any capitalist if unrestricted competition is
good, and the answer will be, “Of course competition is good. All you have to
do to see this clearly is to look at communism, a system that removes competition
from economic endeavor.”
Any
capitalist would tell you that competition is necessary in order to achieve
quality, efficiency, and variety. Communism does not achieve these three
desirable results, but is that because communism lacks the competitive forces
of capitalism? Perhaps it lacks a great many other things too. Unfettered
competition does indeed fuel the fires of quality, efficiency, and variety, but
the reasons for achieving these ends are all wrong. Wouldn’t it be better to
achieve them for the right reasons, for a higher purpose, such as the good of
society and the full preservation of choice in the marketplace?
The
conservatives, in particular, talk a good game when it comes to unregulated
competition. In fact, given the opposing view, their talk makes a good deal of
sense. They pledge allegiance to the banner of laissez-faire capitalism, all in
the name of freedom. But do they walk their talk? Do they really believe their
own words? The evidence here, I’m afraid, is against them. As David Barash
explains:
We
are supposed to believe that conservatives believe in the virtues of
competition, tooth and nail, dog eat dog, and may the best man win. . . . But
do they really believe in such a free-for-all? Consider the Lockheed and
Savings and Loan bailouts, or the various and numerous forms of “corporate
socialism” whereby government provides special benefits and tax breaks to large
corporations, especially those engaged in military contracting. What
conservatives really prefer is competition among the nonrich, the wage earners,
the smaller and less well established . . . especially since out of this
competitive fray generally come lower wages and a more docile workforce.1
Many
people claim to believe in unhindered competition, but when push comes to
shove, we discover that they’d actually prefer to have the government step in
and ensure their success and prosperity, rather than having to “earn” it (and
possibly lose it) in the mercenary marketplace they extol. It is only certain
classes of individuals, apparently, who should be unprotected from the hostile,
predatory environment. So who really does believe in a totally free market?
Perhaps no one.
Both
individuals and businesses usually believe in free competition only to the
degree that they feel they can win. If I were scheduled to play Andre Agassi at
tennis, for instance, I wouldn’t be so gung-ho about competition.
Self-interest, as one might expect, lies at the heart of the competition issue.
If unfettered competition is in our best interest, we’re for it; if, on the
other hand, our competitors are in a position of strength, we immediately want
the rules changed. Sure, I’ll take on Andre—if he wears leg chains, a
straitjacket, and holds the racquet in his teeth.
A
Better Metaphor
Three metaphors have often been
used to define our win-lose competitive system: (1) the athletic contest or
“game,” (2) war, which bears striking similarities to sports, and (3) the
jungle. One major problem with these win-lose metaphors is that they all serve
as excuses for not creating a system in which our unique American ideals can be
practiced. They disavow any higher goal that should focus and mold our
competitiveness.
The
game metaphor is inappropriate, for life is not a game. Food and shelter and
health care and education should not be the prize for winning a contest. The
war metaphor is also improper, for doing battle over the necessities of life,
or even the luxuries, is barbarous. We are a society, we claim to be civilized,
and we must either unite and thrive or splinter, decline, and die as a society.
The jungle metaphor is perhaps most repulsive, for human beings are not simply
members of the animal kingdom. Our intelligence, creativity, self-awareness,
advanced communication skills, preservation of history, and capacity to rise
above instinct and exercise reason and compassion set us apart from other
animals. Why, then, should we be satisfied with economic relationships based on
a metaphor that applies better to lions or sharks or raccoons? Why can’t we
adopt a metaphor that places our economic interaction on a par with our social
and political aspirations?
What
we need is a better metaphor to guide us in economic endeavors. Consider,
perhaps, the orchestra metaphor. There is indeed competition between the
violinists in an orchestra. They all desire to occupy the first chair. But this
competition is not an unfettered, totally self-interested, win-lose type of
competition. The last thing any serious violinist wants is for another
violinist to play wrong notes, for this would reflect on the whole orchestra. A
higher good governs the competition. Each violinist wants the orchestra—and,
hence, all of its parts—to play superbly, flawlessly. But each violinist wants
to be recognized as the best—not because others foul up, but because he or she
is simply more excellent than the others. This healthy competition rests on the
idea of being considered the best of the best. And it is all possible because a
greater common good, a higher ideal governs the competition and binds the
players together.
The
only way we can have this type of competition in our economic pursuits is for
us as citizens to recognize a higher ideal. If we can learn to view the
American Dream as something more than an economic game of grabs, perhaps we can
experience a quality of life and social excellence that has eluded us.
Free
Competition Leads to Authoritarianism
Unfortunately, however, we do not
yet live in such a society. We live in a system that permits unlimited capital
ownership, and we behave according to the win-lose metaphors. And it is not
surprising that this type of mercenary competition carries its own inherent
flaw: The freely competitive marketplace becomes less competitive over time, the
inevitable result being an increase in inequality—in other words, a swift
departure from a central goal of the American Dream.
David
Korten explains that “a competitive market is competitive only when there are
enough buyers and sellers that each has many alternatives. However, by its
nature, untempered competition creates winners and losers. Winners tend to grow
in economic power while losers disappear. The bigger the winners, the more
difficult it is for new entrants to gain a foothold. Market control tends to
concentrate in a few firms, so that the conditions for competition are eroded.”2
The
longer the free market remains totally free, the less competitive it becomes.
This is inevitable, but to say that it becomes less competitive does not
mean that it becomes more cooperative. On the contrary, as power
concentrates, only the most successful predators thrive, and the resulting
imbalance fosters autocratic rather than democratic relationships. Unrestricted
competitive economies tend quite naturally toward authoritarian systems.
Because
untempered competition destroys the competitive marketplace, there must be some
sort of restraint placed on competition. And we have two choices. We can either
change the structure of our system to make cooperation and fair play more
attractive and then bridle our own behavior by following common sense and
proven moral truth or we can pass laws and regulations to bind our hands. The
latter, which we are now pursuing with a vengeance, is really no choice at all,
for you can’t legislate morality. You can’t enforce it either. When internal
moral checks and structural barriers to immoral behavior are nonexistent, no
amount of enforcement on either Wall Street or Main Street will stop
individuals and institutions from finding loopholes in the system, from
behaving like predators. If we want a mercenary marketplace where competition
is virtually nonexistent, then let’s make no changes in the status quo. But if
we are even half serious about creating a moral, fair, cooperative marketplace,
then we need both structural limits and internal moral barriers to protect us
from the abuses that we’ve grown accustomed to.
Benevolence
In a significant paper titled
“The Sympathetic Organization,” David K. Hart points to a philosophically sound
path that would lead us to the type of economic relationships we need. He
argues convincingly that “human nature [has] not one, but two, primordial
aspects: the need to love self (self-love) and the need to love others
(benevolence).”3 A major problem with modern capitalism is that it
has enthroned self-love (“What’s in it for me?”) and abandoned benevolence.
Hart insists that this organizational neglect of a fundamental human need has
created a society in which individuals are alienated not only from one another,
but from themselves and their work. “Alienation results when an individual is
separated from something essential to the development of his or her full
human potential. It is not, then, just a minor psychological dyspepsia, but
rather the spiritual sickness that comes with the ruination of one’s life
possibilities. Our modern age experiences it through the soul-destroying
entanglements of modern organizational life.”4
Organizations,
in essence, dehumanize individuals by treating them as functions. “In modern organizations,
individuals are linked to other individuals in artificial relationships defined
solely by the organizational mission.”5 Friendship and benevolence
are not only unnecessary in such an environment, but often harmful to organizational
objectives.
“The
management orthodoxy,” Hart concludes, “is not only incorrect but unendurable.
Based upon a mutilated version of the whole self, the orthodoxy reduces
individuals to their organizational functions and estranges them from the
rewards of their work. Work is devalued into an instrumental activity valuable
only for what it contributes to organizational goals. It has no intrinsic
meaning. The individual’s labor is a commodity and this makes the individual a
commodity also.”6 Human beings who are treated as commodities cannot
reach their full human potential, nor can they become truly happy.
What
I wish to establish by inserting a portion of Hart’s argument at this point is
not merely that the absence of benevolence and the abundance of alienation in
modern society are negatives that we should correct. In the context of this
book, the relevant point is that self-interest’s domination in modern
capitalism is not mere coincidence. Self-interest and unlimited ownership are products
of each other. Self-interest, of course, lies behind the desire to accumulate
unlimited capital, but unlimited capital ownership also begets greater
self-interest.
What
I have proposed thus far is that we abolish unlimited capital ownership. This
is a structural change. But if we change the structure without also correcting
the moral and behavioral flaw it promotes, then the untempered self-interest
rampant in society will pervert and perhaps destroy the new structure we
attempt to introduce.
What
we must undertake is not just an economic reformation; we must attack the very
roots of our un-American economic system. We will be unsuccessful in this
venture, however, unless we can embrace a higher goal than “What’s in it for
me?” and unless we can restore that part of our nature that unrestricted
capitalism has taught us to ignore: benevolence.
Restrained
Competition
The reason for both restructuring
the parameters of capital ownership and encouraging individuals to adopt
benevolence as a guiding star in their economic dealings is to curb the
competitive nature of our economy. As discussed earlier, the most compelling
argument for a highly competitive economy is that competition is responsible
for all the things that make our lives comfortable, secure, and healthy.
Without competition, we are told, people are not motivated to succeed, and
there is little impetus behind technological advancement. Competition, because
it pits one individual or company against another in a struggle for survival,
yields a never-ending stream of new products, each intended to give its
producer an advantage over “the competition.”
While
I admit that competition does spur technological growth, and that the
by-products of corporate warfare have benefitted society in many ways, I have
come to two other beliefs: first, that competition has also brought us the
waste and inefficiency of planned obsolescence, the curse of a decimated
environment, artificial growth that is becoming a straitjacket rather than a
liberating force, and an economy based on adversarial relationships rather than
cooperative ones; and second, that competition is not the only impetus
for improving the human condition.
Indeed,
I submit that a noncompetitive environment would actually free people to be more
innovative, more creative, and more directly motivated to make life better for
one another. Regardless of the competitive or noncompetitive nature of
their environment, human beings have an innate desire to improve their
individual and collective condition. And in a noncompetitive environment the
risks of failure that deter all but the most daring innovators would be gone.
In short, if we removed the rewards for self-interested innovation, I believe
more people would be inclined to share Ben Franklin’s attitude and motives for
bettering the lives of their neighbors:
To
avoid or overcome the perpetual problems caused by miscalculations of
self-interest, Benjamin Franklin chose the course of modesty and
disinterestedness as a means for progressing. True, Franklin wanted to succeed
in his business and he worked hard to do so. . . . But in all his endeavors,
his objectives were to do good and to be useful as opposed to
getting rich or gathering honors. His emphasis was on contributing rather than
obtaining; on giving rather than receiving. Strange as it may seem, it was
Franklin’s “indifference to the things of this world” that unleashed his full
creative powers. . . .
Benjamin Franklin was one of those rare
individuals who had it within his power to become immensely wealthy, but who
declined the opportunity to do so. To his mother he had written that he would
rather have it said of him that he had lived usefully than that he had died
rich. When his business attained a level to assure him of financial
independence he turned his interests to science and government. Believing
“That, as we enjoy great advantages from the inventions of others, we should be
glad of an opportunity to serve others by any invention of ours; and this we
should do freely and generously,” he made no effort to patent or profit from
any of his inventions. The Franklin stove alone could have made him a fortune,
but he chose not to patent it, and printed the plans for it in his own
newspaper.7
A
noncompetitive system based on limited capital ownership and benevolent
behavior would breed this sort of outlook on life. It is our current system and
its rewards that work to prevent this sympathetic way of living, which to
varying degrees lies dormant in the hearts of men and women everywhere. A
noncompetitive system, in which people didn’t have to fight and scratch for
their “just due,” would unlock many of these latent qualities and put them into
action. Large authoritarian organizations, on the other hand, must manipulate or
force creativity and innovation to the surface.
If
people were freed from the desperate craving to secure their future and the
perceived necessity of acquiring more than they actually need, they might be
surprisingly inclined, even eager, to focus their energies on assisting their
fellow men and women—and find great happiness in doing so. In such a society,
“What’s in it for me?” would become obsolete thinking.
_________________
1.
David P. Barash, The L Word: An Unapologetic, Thoroughly Biased, Long-Overdue
Explication and Defense of Liberalism (New York: Morrow, 1992), 176.
2.
David C. Korten, “A Deeper Look at ‘Sustainable Development,’” World
Business Academy Perspectives 6, no. 2 (1992): 26–27, adapted by Willis
Harman from “Sustainable Development,” World Policy Journal (Winter
1991–92).
3.
David K. Hart, “The Sympathetic Organization,” in Papers on the Ethics of
Administration, ed. N. Dale Wright (Provo: Brigham Young University, 1988),
68.
4.
Hart, “Sympathetic Organization,” 71.
5.
Hart, “Sympathetic Organization,” 77.
6.
Hart, “Sympathetic Organization,” 87.
7.
George L. Rogers, ed., Benjamin Franklin’s The Art of Virtue (Eden
Prairie, Minn.: Acorn Publishing, 1990), 115, 158–59.
No comments:
Post a Comment