The doctrine of
premortality is unsettled primarily because Joseph Smith died before he made
clear exactly what he understood regarding our premortal state, and apparently
none of his successors have felt comfortable filling in all the gaps (or
perhaps they have disagreed on the details). It is also possible that Joseph
himself was uncertain regarding some of the particulars and that God, for some
reason, was reluctant to reveal too many specifics about the nature of our
premortal past. The revelations are intriguing but unclear on some points.
According to D&C 93:29, for instance, “intelligence, or the light of truth,
was not created or made, neither indeed can be” (D&C 93:29). But does this
refer to some sort of unembodied yet individualized prespirit entity or a
rudimentary, impersonal spiritual element? Whatever it means, the context
suggests something more than the general conceptual notion of knowledge or
understanding held by the earliest Mormons.1 The idea that
intelligence cannot be created suggests it is a self-existent capacity or
entity. Along these same lines, in the King Follett discourse, given just weeks
before his murder (and captured in longhand imperfectly by William Clayton),
Joseph taught, “The mind of man—the intelligent part is coequal with, God
himself. . . . Is it logic to say that a spirit is immortal and yet have a
beginning[?] because if a spirit have a beginning it will have an end. . . . Intelligence exists upon a
self-existent principle—is a spirit from age to age & no creation about it.”2
Although Joseph seemed to use the terms mind,
intelligence, and spirit
interchangeably, he was very clear that the “mind of man,” the intelligent part
that gives us agency, identity, and being, had no beginning. Whether that
intelligent mind was already packaged in a spirit body is uncertain. Joseph
left both doors open on that question.
Three Pairs of Possibilities
Because of the
imprecision of Joseph’s statements and the equally imprecise records that
preserved these statements, we are left with two initial possibilities: (1) our
spirits always existed in an embodied form, or (2) our spirits were organized
by Deity through either a process analogous to mortal birth or some other
creative act. The second option leads to two further possibilities: (1) prior
to the creation of our spirits, we were already self-aware, individual,
intelligent entities with agency and accountability; or (2) our spirits were
organized from an impersonal spirit substance called intelligence, at which
point we became sentient, accountable individuals. Dividing these possibilities
along different lines, there are two ultimate alternatives: (1) at some point,
we became individual, accountable entities; or (2) we have always existed as
self-aware, individual beings, either as uncreated spirits or as intelligences
who later acquired spirit bodies.
During my
investigation of our premortal past (and perhaps heavily influenced by Samuel Brown’s
essay), the more I learned about the idea of spirit birth and its theological
history, the less persuasive I found it. But that is not the most important
question anyway. Whether I am a literal child of Heavenly Parents through a
process of spirit birth, or whether my spirit body was organized using some
other mechanism and was then adopted into the heavenly family does not really
matter to me. Adoption is a perfectly viable method of joining a family, either
in mortality or in a prior life. The more important question—indeed, the most important question, regarding our
premortal existence—is whether, on the one hand, I was always “me,” an individual
with a unique personality, strengths and weaknesses, and the inviolable right
to choose my path, or, on the other hand, at some point in the past I was
conjured into existence out of impersonal elements and given free will at that
point, with its accompanying accountability. This is a crucial question for
several reasons, and I believe the evidence overwhelmingly favors the idea that
we have always existed as accountable beings with free will. Let me give two of
several possible arguments supporting this assertion.
Agency and Accountability
If we assume that
God organized our spirits from some kind of impersonal spiritual element called
intelligence, and that before this creative act those spirits did not exist as
conscious, individual beings, then God did in fact create something—a
conscious, self-aware, independent, accountable personality—where before there
was nothing. And if this is the case, the creation of the spirit signifies the
inception of agency, if this is even possible.
We know that
spirits had agency in the premortal existence. But if God created a conscious
entity from unconscious elements, knowing perfectly at the outset that this
particular new being possessed substantial flaws and weaknesses and had no
chance whatever (in God’s mind, at least, since he sees the end from the
beginning)3 to gain exaltation, then God would be, in a very real
sense, at least partially accountable for that being’s damnation. Why? Because
he created that spirit child with insurmountable weaknesses, which he or she
had no choice in acquiring. In essence, if God, using impersonal “intelligence”
as his potter’s clay, chooses for some reason to make one spirit vessel adequately
strong and another hopelessly flawed, then the ultimate exaltation or damnation
of the individual is largely his doing.
Elder Neal A.
Maxwell used this same argument to combat the notion that God created all
things out of nothing:
Latter-day Saints also know that God
did not create man ex nihilo, out
of nothing. The concept of an “out of nothing” creation confronts its adherents
with a severe dilemma. One commentator wrote of human suffering and an “out of
nothing” creation: “We cannot say that [God] would like to help but cannot: God
is omnipotent. We cannot say that he would help if he only knew: God is
omniscient. We cannot say that he is not responsible for the wickedness of
others: God creates those others. Indeed an omnipotent, omniscient God [who
creates all things absolutely—i.e., out of nothing] must be an accessory before
(and during) the fact to every human misdeed; as well as being responsible for
every non-moral defect in the universe.”4
Antony Flew, the atheist
philosopher quoted here (who late in life became a deist),5 is
pointing out the inescapable flaw in the notion of ex nihilo creation, but the same illogic applies to the idea that
God created conscious and imperfect but accountable beings out of impersonal,
unaccountable raw materials. On a significant level, this idea is precisely
analogous to creatio ex nihilo and
leads to the inescapable conclusion that God is at least partially (and perhaps
primarily) accountable for the evil in the world. Indeed, some of his children
have an astonishing capacity and proclivity for evil. Given the choice, why
would God create such beings?
Blake Ostler, in
volume 2 of his series on Mormon thought, similarly argues that a fundamental
incompatibility exists between free will and the doctrine of creatio ex nihilo:
If the causes of our acts originate from causes outside of
our control, then we are not free and cannot be praised or blamed for what we
do resulting from those causes. . . . Thus, a person must be an ultimate source
of her acts to be free. . . .The source of the action is the agent’s own will
that is not caused by events or acts outside of the agent but from the agent’s
own acts of will. . . . If the libertarian demand that we must be the ultimate
source of our choices to be morally responsible for them is sound, then God
cannot create morally responsible persons ex
nihilo.6
Ostler’s argument is valid whether
we are talking about the Christian notion of God creating the physical world
and mortal souls out of nothing or the LDS view that God created (organized)
all things spiritually before they were created physically. Free will, or
agency, can only truly exist for God’s children if they are what theologians
call “first causes,” uncreated individuals.
Mormons do not
believe in a deterministic God. We believe in a God who has perfect
foreknowledge.7 But since the God described by those who favor the
“impersonal intelligence” theory does indeed play a deterministic role in the
lives of his children—by the choice of elements he employs in their creation—he
is, therefore, ultimately accountable for their failures.
We may argue that
no weakness is insurmountable, that we can choose to accept God’s grace and
overcome our weaknesses, so that “weak things become strong” unto us (Ether
12:27). Our ultimate destiny is then a product of our choices, regardless of
any disadvantage we may have been given at the outset. But if we were burdened
before we were ever capable of choice with fundamental weaknesses—perhaps even
a basic incapacity to plant the seed of faith—how can we be accountable for not
having sufficient faith to accept God’s grace and overcome that weakness? It is
an eternal Catch–22. Our strengths and weaknesses always influence our choices.
Sometimes we are simply too weak to choose correctly. Sometimes we are too weak
to even ask for strength. If God created us as sentient beings from nonsentient
material, knowing from the outset that we would not choose to become as he
is—and this is a very real scenario for the majority of his children who live
to the age of accountability—we might very well ask why he would create us that
way. For his entertainment? Because he needs other beings to worship him? Or
perhaps so that he would be needed by us? But we do not believe in a sadistic
or narcissistic or insecure God. So why wouldn’t he create us differently, make
us more like his flawless Firstborn? Precisely because he did not create us from impersonal raw
materials.
Sin, Satan, and Punishment
The notion of sin
also argues against this theory. Sin is more than simple bad behavior (doing
things we know we should not do). The question that is rarely asked, or
answered, is what causes us to do things we know we shouldn’t do? Temptation?
No, temptation does not cause sin. The
root cause of sin is our inability or unwillingness to resist temptation. In
other words, sin results from weakness. If we had no weakness, we likely would
not sin. Christ was sinless because he was not weak. He was tempted in all
points, undoubtedly more severely than any of God’s other children, yet he
never succumbed (see Heb. 4:15). When we have no knowledge of appropriate
behaviors and attitudes, of course we are not accountable. Sin occurs when we
know the law but act against our own better judgment. Sometimes we act against
better judgment out of rebellion (although it can be argued that rebelliousness
is simply a particular manifestation of weakness), but usually our sins do not
come from rebellion. Most often we are simply too weak to withstand temptation,
too weak to break out of dysfunctional behavioral patterns, too weak to invoke
God’s saving grace. So, if our weaknesses are God’s doing because he used an
inferior quality or selection of “intelligence” when he formed our spirits,
then we cannot be accountable for our failure to measure up. “It’s not my
fault,” any of us could argue, “that God didn’t use top-quality intelligence
when he organized my spirit. It’s not my fault that he didn’t make me more like
Jesus.” Indeed, in such a universe, dear Brutus, the fault is not in ourselves, but in our stars.8
The very
existence of Satan creates difficulties for the intelligence-as-impersonal-raw-material
argument. God sees the end from the beginning. He knew, when he organized the
spirit son named Lucifer, that he was creating a vessel doomed to suffer the
horrible torments of eternal hell. Would a compassionate God create from
oblivion a conscious being, a son he would love, if he knew with a perfect
foreknowledge that this son would spend eternity in hellish agony? Not if
intelligence was merely a mass of raw, impersonal material to be used as God
saw fit. Such an act would be nothing less than sadism. The same, of course,
holds true for his other children, many of whom, he knew at the outset, would
suffer varying degrees of eternal damnation.
The only logical
explanation for the fact that we are completely accountable for our decisions
and must suffer the consequences of those choices is that we have always
existed, that our weaknesses and strengths are an intrinsic part of us, and
that we have always been accountable for them. This makes perfect sense. If I
am either an eternally existing spirit or recipient of a spirit body and have the
opportunity to both expand my innate strengths and overcome my inherent
weaknesses—through my own efforts and through the saving grace of Christ—it is
I who am wholly accountable for my success or failure, and my free will is
totally unimpaired. In this theory, instead of God being a preferential
determiner of destinies, an omnipotent playwright who dreams up an infinitely
varied cast to perform his bizarre eternal tragicomedy, he becomes a
compassionate volunteer, aiding in our eternal progress, but never infringing
on our eternal agency to become whatever we choose. The only logical
explanation for our unfettered free will, our complete accountability, and a
just God’s willingness to punish us for disobedience is the eternal existence of identity. And this,
I believe, is what Joseph Smith was trying to teach. Eternal sentient existence
redefines our relationship with God. If we were just impersonal intelligence
before God “created” our spirit bodies, then his relationship to us is far
different than if we existed forever as self-aware beings with agency and
inherent strengths and weaknesses.
________________________
1. “All truth is independent
in that sphere in which God has placed it, to act for itself, as all
intelligence also; otherwise there is no existence” (D&C 93:30). Here,
intelligence appears to have the ability to act independently, and so does
truth, which raises questions about what truth actually is. Of course, this may
merely be another example of Joseph using words imprecisely.
2. Andrew F. Ehat and Lyndon
W. Cook, The Words of Joseph Smith: The
Contemporary Accounts of the Nauvoo Discourses of the Prophet Joseph (Orem,
Utah: Grandin Book, 1991), 359. I would argue with Joseph’s logic here. Simple
mathematics demonstrates that something can have a beginning but no end. A
straight line that begins at point A but goes on forever in a certain direction
is an example. Another is a series of whole numbers, beginning at 3 and
increasing by 3 forever—3, 6, 9, 12 . . . and so on to infinity. So logic does
not insist that because we have no end we also have no beginning. Joseph’s ring
analogy, as with all analogies, has its limits.
3. See, for instance, Abraham
2:8 and D&C 38:2. See also note 7
below.
4. Neal A. Maxwell, “The
Richness of the Restoration,” Ensign 28
(March 1998): 14, quoting Antony Flew, “Theology and Falsification,” in New
Essays in Philosophical Theology, ed. Antony Flew and Alasdair Macintyre
(1955; repr., New York: Macmillan, 1973), 107.
5. William Grimes, “Antony Flew, Philosopher and Ex-Atheist, Dies
at 87,” New York Times, April 16,
2010, available at http://www.nytimes.com/2010/04/17/arts/17flew.html?_r=0.
6. Blake T. Ostler, The
Problems of Theism and the Love of God, vol. 2 of Exploring Mormon Thought (Salt Lake City: Greg Kofford Books,
2006), 410–11.
7. There is some debate among
LDS philosophers and theologians about God’s omniscience, what the term means,
and whether it includes a perfect foreknowledge of events. Terryl Givens, for
instance, refers to the Encyclopedia of
Mormonism, which “states that ‘Latter-day Saints differ among themselves in
their understanding of the nature of God’s knowledge. Some have thought that
God increases endlessly in knowledge as well as in glory and dominion. Others
hold to the more traditional view that God’s knowledge, including the
foreknowledge of future free contingencies, is complete.’ But it is hard to
find in Mormon writings either any apostolic pronouncement that limits God’s
knowledge of the future or the opinion that divine omniscience would be an
impediment to free will. [Joseph] Smith denied the assumption that God’s
omniscience must condition at least a limited predestination. He asserted
simply, ‘I believe that God foreknew everything, but did not foreordain
everything; I deny that foreordain and foreknow is the same thing.” Givens, Wrestling the Angel, 100, quoting David
L. Paulsen, “Omnipotence of God; Omnipresence of God; Omniscience of God,” Encyclopedia of Mormonism, ed. Daniel H.
Ludlow, 4 vols. (New York: Macmillan, 1992), 3:1030, and a report in a letter
(now lost) by Mathew L. Davis, written to his wife, February 6, 1840, in Ehat
and Cook, Words of Joseph Smith, 33.
In LDS scripture, we also have the Lord describing himself as “the same which
knoweth all things, for all things are present before mine eyes” (D&C
38:2), and “I know the end from the beginning” (Abr. 2:8).
8. My apologies to William
Shakespeare; see Julius Caesar,
I.ii.140–41.
No comments:
Post a Comment